Who cares? I care for several reasons. Milton Friedman stands
out as one of a small number of intellectuals who had a favourable influence on
public policy in the 20
th century. Today – July 31, 2012 - is the
100
th anniversary of his birth. This blog is about freedom and flourishing. And
I am wondering how the (provisional) title of the book I am writing, ‘
Free to Flourish’, might be perceived. It is a fairly obvious title given the content
of the book, but I hope it might be viewed as an appropriate tribute to Milton
Friedman, who with his wife, Rose, wrote a better book, entitled ‘Free to
Choose’, which was first published in 1979.
I have not been able to find instances where Milton Friedman
referred to human flourishing directly in his published works. His references
to happiness seem to be mainly in the context of recognition that people have a
right to pursue it as they see fit. He argued that the freedom of the
individual should be seen as the ultimate goal in judging social arrangements and
that a free society releases the energies and abilities of people to pursue
their own objectives.It is reasonably clear that he thought the vast majority of people would be successful in pursuing their own objectives but he does not seem to have made specific claims to that effect. I expect he would probably have endorsed the sentiment of Friedrich Hayek that 'it may even be that liberty exercises its beneficial effects as much through the discipline it imposes on us as through the more visible opportunities it offers' (Constitution of Liberty, 1960:18).
Friedman was certainly careful not to claim freedom as ‘an
all-embracing ethic’:
‘Indeed, a major aim of the liberal is to leave the ethical
problem for the individual to wrestle with. The “really” important ethical
problems are those that face an individual in a free society – what he should do
with his freedom’ (‘Capitalism and Freedom’, 1962: 12).
For the benefit of readers who have come to view the liberal
label as signifying support for ever-greater government regulation, I should
point out that Friedman was using the word liberalism ‘in its original sense –
as the doctrines pertaining to a free man’.
Friedman was also mindful of the need to acknowledge a
limited case for government action on paternalistic grounds. He wrote:
‘Freedom is a tenable objective only for responsible
individuals. We do not believe in freedom for madmen or children’. He pondered the
point deeply:
‘The paternalistic ground for government activity is in many
ways the most troublesome to a liberal; for it involves the acceptance of a
principle – that some shall decide for others – which he finds objectionable in
most applications and which he rightly regards as a hallmark of his chief intellectual
opponents, the proponents of collectivism in one or another of its guises,
whether it be communism, socialism, or a welfare state. Yet there is no use
pretending that problems are simpler than in fact they are. There is no
avoiding the need for some measure of paternalism’ (‘Capitalism and Freedom’, p
33-4).
However, Friedman would have been alarmed by the modern
tendency for all citizens to be treated like children - with the potential for
a war on obesity (beginning perhaps with an assault on marketing of soft drinks)
to be added to the war on drugs. He argued:
‘Insofar as the government has information not generally
available about the merits or demerits of the items we ingest or the activities
we engage in, let it give us the information. But let it leave us free to
choose what chances we want to take with our own lives’ (‘Free to Choose’, p
227).
Friedman was particularly concerned about the adverse social
effects of paternalistic welfare programs:
‘Their major evil is their effect on the fabric of society.
They weaken the family; reduce the incentive to work, save and innovate; reduce
the accumulation of capital; and limit our freedom’ (‘Free to Choose’, p 127).
It seems to me that one of the most important contributions
that Friedman made was his support for efforts to measure economic freedom. In
a discussion published in
the preface
to
the 2002 ‘Economic Freedom of the World Report’, Friedman
stressed the importance of measurement of economic freedom to development of a
better understanding of the concept:
‘There's a phrase written on the entrance to one of the
social sciences buildings at the University of Chicago: "When you cannot
measure something, your knowledge is meager and unsatisfying." In the
process of measuring, you find that measuring is a form of definition. It isn't
just that there's economic freedom out there to be measured. In the process of
measuring it, we're going to define what economic freedom is. We don't really
know what we have, what economic freedom is, unless we've gotten to the point
of trying to measure it and see what variables it consists of, and what each of
those means. Over the course of time, we have gotten a much more sophisticated
understanding of what we mean when we talk about economic freedom.’
In the same discussion he made a plea for economic freedom
to be seen in the context of freedom more generally:
‘In looking to the future, I believe one has to be careful
not to over-emphasize the role of economic freedom as a source of economic
growth, as compared with the role of economic freedom as a part of freedom, of
human freedom.
We've talked about economic and political freedom as if they
were wholly separate things, which they are not. I think the next big task
facing the economic freedom project will be to try to weld the two together and
make a combined index of economic and political freedom, especially where they
mesh with one another. Property rights are not only a source of economic
freedom. They are also a source of political freedom. That's what really got us
interested in economic freedom in the first place. Some of the elements in the
Freedom House index seem to me to be inconsistent with some of the elements in
our index, and it would seem to be useful to see how to reconcile those two and
put them on the same philosophical basis.’
One of the features of Friedman’s writings is the importance
he placed on political freedoms. His argument for economic freedom was based, in
part, on the view that it is ‘an indispensable means toward the achievement of
political freedom’. He saw political freedom – the absence of coercion of a man
by his fellow men – as requiring the elimination of concentration of power to the
greatest extent possible. He argued that competitive capitalism promotes
political freedom because it disperses power – it separates economic power from
political power and in this way enables the one to offset the other.
Friedman deserves the praise he has received for his academic
accomplishments in economics, but he also deserves praise for his efforts to
persuade his fellow citizens of his views about freedom. He knew that he had an
important message to convey and he did his best to spread it as far as possible.
In the final paragraph of ‘Capitalism and Freedom’ he wrote:
‘I believe we shall be able to preserve and extend freedom …
. But we shall be able to do so only if we awake to the threat we face, only if
we persuade our fellow men that free institutions offer a surer, if perhaps at
times a slower, route to the ends they seek than the coercive power of the
state.’
Milton Friedman put his faith in the ability of his followers to persuade their fellow citizens, rather than in his own ability to influence governments directly.
----------------------
The site:
www.freetochoose.tv is hosting a 24-hour "Friedman Freedom Festival" beginning 12:00 a.m. US Eastern Time July 31st and running until 12:00a.m. Aug. 1st. It will be a continuously
playing list of Friedman talks, musicians from around the world and shorter
clips of Friedman - most of which have rarely seen
before.
Postscript 1:
Jim Belshaw has a post: '
Friedman, Freedom and Paternalism' in which he kindly refers to this post and some of the discussion below. Jim adopts a definition of paternalism as the state 'telling people what to do'. That is paternalistic, but I need to think more about the issue. My initial reaction is that wealth redistribution is also paternalistic - it is akin to a father taking toys off one child (on the grounds that she has too many) and giving them to her younger brother (who is deemed to have too few). I find it much easier to accept that it might be fair for a father (or mother) to make such a redistribution within their family (hopefully with the consent of the kids concerned) than to accept the validity of Wayne Swan's attempts to apply that ethic to the whole of society.
Jim also refers to a post by Lorenzo;
'Friedman's Century', which has links to several other sites with relevant comments.
Regarding my reference above to the obesity epidemic, Greg Dwyer has referred me to an excellent article entitled '
Sugar Sickness' by New Zealand medical doctor, MacDoctor, who points out the futility of proposals for governments to tax sugar etc. One day the paternalists (or are they nannies?) responsible for the wars against personal responsibility will realize that they are making matters worse.
Postscript 2:
Having looked at common usage of 'paternalism', I now think Jim
and kvd are right. It entails limiting the liberty of some person or group
in order to protect them.
Milton Friedman also seems to be right in his claim that the
motivations of Bismark and the British Tories in creating the welfare state
were paternalistic i.e. directed toward protecting people from harm. (Their
motives were also political i.e. cutting the grounds from under their social
democratic opponents). It is interesting that 'paternalistic' doesn't seem to
imply that the action is against the will of the person being protected.
My supposition that Wayne Swan has paternalistic
motives in arguing for wealth redistribution is probably wrong. His motives
might be better described as egalitarian.