When you think of dialectical approaches the idea
that may come to mind is thesis, anti-thesis, and synthesis. As suggested in the sentence quoted above, I am
viewing dialectical approaches more broadly in this essay. Before discussing the
meaning of dialectics, however, it might be helpful for me to outline why I
think problem definition is a topic worth considering.
Importance of problem definition
Fundamental values are clearly at stake in public discussion of some issues (e.g. abortion, the death penalty, assisted dying).
Most people tend to agree about policy goals when it is not obvious that fundamental issues are at
stake. For
example, when people are discussing climate change, they tend to agree that exposure
to extreme weather events has undesirable consequences for human flourishing. Similarly,
when health services are discussed, people tend to agree that illness is
undesirable; when education is discussed they tend to agree that literacy and
numeracy are desirable; and when poverty is discussed, they tend to agree that
it would be desirable for all humans to have the wherewithal to maintain a
minimum standard of living.
However, when a participant in public discussion proposes a remedial strategy, those who disagree often claim that the proposed strategy is built on an implausible view of the nature of the problem being addressed. Much public discussion is about questions such as: Is there really a problem? Is the problem one that individuals are normally expected to manage by themselves, or is some kind of collective action usually considered appropriate? What plausible explanations have been offered as to the causes of the problem? Should we be thinking about how to tackle the causes of the problem or about how to alleviate symptoms? Which potential remedial strategies should be the focus of our attention? Discussion often focuses on the validity of research findings and other information offered to answer such questions.
Relevance of dialectics
I am adopting here the definition of dialectics
proposed by Chris Sciabarra, in his book Total
Freedom: Toward a Dialectical Libertarianism:
“Dialectics is an orientation toward contextual analysis of the systemic and dynamic relations of components within a totality.” (173)
Sciabarra explains that “a totality” “is not simply an undifferentiated or all-encompassing whole”. He suggests it could be a two-person dialogue, an economy, or a social system. I will take the “totality” to encompass everything that can be shown to be relevant to the topic under discussion. If a dialectical approach to problem definition is adopted, the meaning of totality would be a matter for consideration in any specific context.
Sciabarra emphasizes that dialectics “is a thinking
style that emphasizes contextual analysis of systems across time”. In a
dialectical approach, “the aspects of a totality are understood systemically
– that is, according to their spatial, or synchronic, interconnections – and dynamically
– that is, according to their temporal, or diachronic, interconnections”.
Sciabarra offers his definition of dialectics after
considering the use of dialectics from Aristotle to Hegel, and, after Hegel, by
Marx, Hayek, Rand and others.
The question I have posed above - of whether it is
helpful to adopt a dialectical approach to problem definition in public
discussion - is not discussed explicitly in Total Freedom. However, that
context seems to me to be one in which dialects has potential to be more
helpful than alternative approaches.
In this essay I refer to some issues that have
recently been the focus of public discussion to illustrate how a dialectical
approach to problem definition would differ from the range of other methodological
orientations. I focus on the four broad orientations that Sciabarra has
identified: strict atomism, strict organicism, dualism, and monism.
Strict atomism
Strict atomists look at the world as if each aspect of
it is separable from every other aspect. A recent Australian example of such an
approach is the
decision of the government of New South Wales (NSW) to build homes
for “essential” workers in Sydney. The rationale given is: “NSW would grind to a halt without
nurses, paramedics, teachers, police officers and firefighters, but many can’t
afford a place to live in Sydney, close to where they work”. The announcement acknowledges
existence of a more general housing affordability issue in Sydney but the
government’s approach to dealing with that issue is clearly atomistic.
A
dialectical approach would address a range of questions including whether anything
is preventing the labour market from functioning flexibly to remunerate “essential”
workers sufficiently to ensure that sufficient numbers are available to meet demand
for their services in Sydney, and whether government regulation (e.g. zoning regulation)
has been discouraging construction of sufficient affordable housing.
Strict
organicism
Strict
organicism relies on an illusory synoptic vantage point and views all
relationships encompassed within the topic under discussion as constituents of
a holistic principle at work. I see examples of strict organicism in recent
discussion in Australia of the murder of women by their current or former male
partners. Some people have suggested that this is a cultural problem which
requires a fundamental change in men’s attitudes towards women. For example, Senator
David Pocock stated: "we have a huge cultural
issue" that needs to be "tackled". "This is going to take
far more than some extra funding. This is a fundamental shift in the way that
we treat women in this country.”
However, defining
the problem as one that requires further improvements in men’s attitudes toward
women tends to overlook the potential for other remedial action that is likely
to be more effective in protecting the women whose lives are at greatest risk.
A dialectic
approach would recognize that many of the men who kill their partners have known
histories of violence. Research by Kate Fitz-Gibbon et al based on sentencing
remarks by judges indicates that few intimate femicides occur without the
offender having prior interaction with the criminal justice system. This suggests the existence of effective
intervention points that are not dependent on bringing about cultural change.
Dualism
and Monism
Sciabarra considers dualism and monism under
the same heading. “Dualism is an orientation towards analysis by separation of
a system’s components into two spheres”. “Monism is an orientation towards
analysis of a system’s components as manifestations of a single factor”. Monists
often embrace the dichotomies defined by dualists, while advocating a one-sided
monistic resolution.
The
mind-body dichotomy is a classic example of dualism. Another is the division of
the social world into two spheres – the state and civil society (including the
market). Sciabarra notes that dualist statists and dualist anarchists perceive these
two spheres as fundamentally opposed and propose to resolve the conflict
between them via monistic absorption of one sphere by the other. One side
proposes a statist solution whereas the other proposes a civil society solution.
The debate
about climate change provides examples of dualism and monism. For example, consider
differences of opinion about CO2. On one side of the debate, many people argue
that CO2 is polluting the atmosphere and causing adverse climate change. Their
opponents argue that increased concentrations of CO2 in the atmosphere have had
beneficial impacts on crop yields and the growth of forests. A dialectic
approach would recognise that those views are not necessarily in conflict. A
central issue is at what CO2 concentration the adverse impacts are likely to exceed
beneficial impacts.
Dualism and
monism are also evident in the broader debate about action to reduce CO2
emissions. On the one side, some people consider the idea that CO2 emissions influence
the climate as a hoax perpetrated by statists to gain greater control over the
lives of ordinary people. On the other side, some people claim that the world
is heading for disaster if urgent action is not taken to reduce emissions.
A dialectic
approach would emphasize the importance of keeping context in mind when considering
such issues.
Let us first
consider an individual who wants to come to an informed view on whether extreme
views of climate alarmists or sceptics should, or should not, be dismissed as
implausible. That individual could be expected to spend many hours sifting
through available scientific evidence. They might conclude, as I have, that projections
of climate change models endorsed by the IPCC are more plausible than the views
of climate alarmists and sceptics. On the other hand, they may come to different
conclusions, as have some of my friends who seem to be fairly intelligent.
Now, let us
consider the appropriate policy response of the Australian government in the
light of two facts: Australian greenhouse gas emissions contribute just over 1
percent of global emissions, and on a per capita basis, Australia’s emissions
are among the highest in the world. That context has considerable relevance in
considering an appropriate policy response:
Climate
alarmists should be encouraged to understand that even if Australia’s emissions
went to net zero tomorrow, that would have an insignificant direct impact on
global greenhouse gas emissions and would certainly not prevent the global calamity
that they fear. A policy of rapid reduction in emissions may offer Australia the
worst of all worlds – high cost of transition to a low emissions economy accompanied
by high cost of adaptation to climate change.
Climate sceptics
should be encouraged to understand that international sanctions may be imposed
on Australia if this country is seen to be unduly slow in taking action to
reduce emission levels.
Conclusions
In this essay I have considered whether a
dialectical approach is relevant to problem definition in public discussion. I
have adopted Chris Sciabarra’s view of dialectics as
a thinking style that emphasizes contextual analysis of systems across time.
The examples of problem definition that I have
considered – housing for “essential” workers in Sydney, murder of women by their current or
former male partners, and the debate about climate change – support the view
that a dialectical approach is preferable to strict atomism, strict organicism,
dualism and monism.
It could be
claimed that context-keeping is something that people who are skilled in problem
definition do as a matter of course without declaring that they are adopting a
dialectical approach. I have some sympathy with that claim but I note that I
have had no difficulty finding examples where people who might be expected to
have some skills in problem definition have adopted approaches that can be
described as strict atomism, strict organicism, dualism and monism.
Some people
need reminding about the importance of context-keeping.