The
practitioners of behavioral economics have tended to direct their research
findings mainly at “choice architects”, including paternalistic governments.
For example, in their book, Nudge, Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein adopt
the term “libertarian paternalism” to propose:
“Choice
architects can preserve freedom of choice while also nudging people in
directions that will improve their lives”.
An example
might help to clarify what a nudge involves. If the government were to invest a
certain proportion of your income in a superannuation fund on your behalf this
would amount to a nudge, rather than a push or a shove, if you were allowed to
withdraw the funds at any time to use as you wished. Because of a tendency for
people to avoid choices, or to choose default options, such an arrangement
would be likely to result in more investment in superannuation than one that
relied solely on tax incentives. It would do this without the interference in
personal choice that is involved in compulsory superannuation, such as exists
in Australia. (That example is taken from my review of Nudge.)
However, if
you view human flourishing as an essentially self-directed activity, as I do,
you may be sceptical about claims that such nudging can improve your life. Even
if the people doing the nudging have your interests at heart, their perception
of what will improve your life will not necessarily accord with your own
preferences.
In the
example provided above, additional transactions costs may be imposed on the
person being nudged. For example, investment in superannuation might not be the
best option for a young person wanting to save for a deposit on a house. Over
the longer term, the value of an investment in a superannuation fund could be
expected to rise to a greater extent than cash in the bank, but short term
fluctuations in equity prices make superannuation a less suitable vehicle for
shorter term saving. Withdrawing funds for a house deposit could result in
capital losses being incurred.
Robert
Sugden suggests that “something is clearly wrong if economists think that their
response to the discovery of mistakes in individual decision-making must take
the form of a recommendation about public policy” (The Community of
Advantage, p 44). If you want to help individuals to make better decisions
it makes more sense to address the information to those individuals rather than
to address it to autocrats. (I have
previously discussed The Community of Advantage here, here and here.)
Sugden makes
the point that nudgees (people who are nudged) do not always explain their failure
to follow expert advice in terms of self-control problems. For example, an
obese person who fails to follow expert advice about choosing fruit rather than
cake, could explain his choice in a range of different ways that do not involve
a self-control problem. If he sees nothing wrong with his choices, he has no
reason to want to be nudged by having the fruit placed in a more prominent
position in the cafeteria relative to the cake (p 47).
However, if
the obese person acknowledges that he has a self-control problem, research
findings about the influence of placement of products on consumer purchases
might help him to modify his behaviour. His trusted advisers might be able to
suggest how he could nudge himself to make better choices. By coincidence, earlier
today, I heard a news item indicating that there is a supermarket chain in
Australia that refrains from placing confectionary near checkouts. That
information could be relevant to a person with an acknowledged self-control
problem, who was wanting to avoid impulse purchases of confectionary.
The fact
that supermarkets often place confectionary near checkouts illustrates that
choice architects may not always have paternalistic motives. It should not be
assumed, however, that their motives are exploitive. Supermarkets want loyal
customers, so it is not likely to be in their interests to have shoppers end up
feeling that they have been manipulated to make unhealthy choices and/or to
spend more money than they wanted to spend. It is possible that the placement
of the confectionary helps give most shoppers good feelings about their
shopping experience. The nudge that one person views as manipulative may be
viewed by others as benign, or even as providing a helpful reminder.
As a rule,
it is good to be aware how you are being nudged in the choices you make. It is
necessary to be aware that you are being nudged, as the first step in making a
conscious choice to accept or reject the suggestion involved. Behavioural
economics can make a useful contribution in helping to make us aware of how
nudges may affect the choices we make.
Sugden
suggests that behavioural economists who discover possible mistakes in
individual decision-making are in an analogous situation to epidemiologists who
discover an apparent causal relationship between some activity and the
prevalence of an illness. The epidemiological findings are made available to
the public in various ways and begin to influence behaviour prior to any public
policy intervention being contemplated (p 43).
Similarly, happiness
researchers who discover that average life satisfaction of various groups is
affected by factors such as leisure, or commute times, are providing
information that individuals may wish to consider in the choices they make. Individuals are likely to be affected differently,
but rarely so differently that information about others is irrelevant.
Sugden acknowledges
that normative economics has almost always been directed toward public
decision-makers rather than private individuals, but suggests that “since
economists often characterize their discipline as the science of rational
choice one might expect them to recognize the potential value of helping
individuals to make better decisions in their private lives” (p 43). He notes
that Philip Wicksteed, one of the founders of neoclassical economics, presented
economics as a study of the “general laws of the administration of resources”
and insisted that these laws apply “from end to end of life”. He gave practical
advice on how to avoid common mistakes in decision-making. The passage quoted
above reflects the role he saw for economists in helping people to make better
choices.
Sugden’s
view that there is a role for economists in helping individuals to make better
choices seems somewhat at variance with the view of James Buchanan. In his
article “What
should economists do?”, published in 1964, Buchanan argued that the theory
of choice should be removed from “its position of eminence in the economist’s
thought processes”. He suggested that economists should concentrate their
attention on human behaviour in market relationships and other voluntaristic
exchange processes, and upon the various institutional arrangements that can
arise as a result of this form of activity.
I maintain the
view, as previously expressed, that Buchanan is correct in identifying the
heartland of economics to be concerned with voluntaristic exchange processes, but
that does not rule out the potential for economists to make useful
contributions in helping individuals to make better personal choices. It is in
the latter context that behavioural economics is most relevant to human flourishing.