A week ago my answer would have been along the lines that while I could not claim any expertise in American history I had the impression that the
natural right to liberty had been recognised in both the US Declaration of
Independence and the US Constitution. In support of that view I would have
pointed to the division of powers between the executive, congress and
judiciary; the specific guarantees of freedom including freedom of speech; and
the allocation of specific powers to the central government with remaining
powers residing with the states. I would have argued that limiting the powers
to the central government was a particularly important guarantee of freedom
because states which imposed burdensome taxation and regulation were likely to
lose out in the competition for people and investment. However, I would also have
indicated that I was aware that the federal government had ended up with more
power than the founding fathers had intended as a consequence of imaginative
judicial interpretations of the Constitution.
For the benefits of an Australian audience I might have
added that the framers of the US Constitution were obviously more concerned
about liberty that the framers of the Australian Constitution. The two
constitutions are similar, but the Australian Constitution - written a little
over a century later - does not include explicit guarantees of liberty. As with
the US Constitution, the Australian Constitution specifies limited powers for the
central government, but some leading politicians who were heavily involved in
federation were aware from the outset of the potential for its taxing powers to
give the central government great leverage. Soon after federation, Alfred
Deakin remarked that the Constitution had left the States “legally free but
financially bound to the chariot wheels of the Central Government”.
My view of the libertarian credentials of the framers of the
US Constitution has been challenged over the past week by my reading of Sheldon
Richman’s book, America’sCounter-Revolution: The Constitution Revisited. Richman suggests that the
framers of the US Constitution staged a counter-revolution:
“the Constitution, far from limiting government, was
actually designed to bring about a new one that betrayed the ideals of the
Declaration of Independence itself. … There is a reason it has done a poor job
in protecting freedom: it was never intended to do so”.
The Constitution was ratified in 1788, twelve years after
the Declaration of Independence. It replaced the Articles of Confederation,
which had been ratified in 1781. Under the Articles the government of the
United States had been essentially confined to external affairs. It had no
power to tax, regulate trade, or raise an army.
Greater central government powers were apparently not
required to improve the lives of citizens. Under the Articles of Confederation,
America was relatively peaceful and prosperous. In Richman’s words, life “wasn’t
so bad after all – at least for white males with property … ; obviously it wasn’t so good for African
Americans, Indians, and white women, but their fate did not change in 1789”.
Richman cites evidence that a negative impression of the
confederation period was fostered by those who favoured nationalist
centralisation. Mercantile interests apparently tended to favour nationalist
centralisation because they hoped it would help them to hold onto political power
at the expense of radical democrats – including overtaxed small farmers - who were
gaining greater representation in some state legislatures. Interstate
protectionism was more legend than fact.
The author suggests that from the outset the US Constitution
could reasonably be seen as a stool with three legs: taxation; mercantilist
trade-promotion; and national security in a hostile world. The Constitution
gave Congress taxation powers that would be sufficient (in my view) for any
modern warfare/welfare state: “Power To lay and collect Taxes, Duties, Imposts
and Excises, to pay the Debts and provide for the common Defence and general
Welfare of the United States”. Promoting trade was seen in those days (and
still today in many quarters) to be more about opening export markets than
enabling mutually beneficial transactions between people in different countries; trade-promotion
was about selective embargoes and building empires. The nationalists sought a
permanent military establishment that would be powerful enough to protect the
nation’s interests from the old colonial powers and the Indian nations, whose
lands Americans coveted.
The bill of rights in the US Constitution was introduced as an
afterthought to mollify anti-federalists who had made the absence of a bill of
rights the top talking point against the draft constitution. The rights embodied
were largely uncontroversial common law rights of Englishmen.
Richman seems to me to make a strong case that James Madison,
sometimes referred to as the father of the US Constitution, was father of the “implied-powers
doctrine”. Madison argued that it was impossible to confine the federal government
to the exercise of powers “expressly delegated” unless the constitution “descended
to recount every minutiae”. Richman comments:
“Madison was right, of course. … There must be implied
powers. But that’s the danger of a constitution and a monopoly constitutional
government. Implied powers must be inferred, and inference requires
interpretation. Who is likely to have the inside track in that process: those
who seek to restrict government power or those who seek to expand it? We know
the answer to that question”.
This book does more than make the case that a counter-revolution set America on the wrong path over 200 years ago. The author
asks an important question that could help put America back on the right path: “Where
is the Constitution?” Richman is referring to “the real constitution – the set of dispositions that influence what
most Americans will accept as legitimate actions by the politicians and
bureaucrats who make up the government”. The point he is making, with the aid of Roderick
Long’s (easily found) contribution on “market anarchism as constitutionalism”,
is that if government power is to be wound back the real constitution must be pro-liberty:
“That’s why there’s no substitute for education and an
intellectual-moral revolution”.
Another piece of wisdom that Sheldon Richman provides to
libertarians is to avoid letting the perfect be the enemy of the good:
“I see no reason for libertarians, in the name of purity, to
withhold support for steps that make real progress toward liberty and pave the
way for more”.
That is an approach that a I can readily support without
having to be persuaded that market anarchy offers the best prospects for human
flourishing.