In an essay entitled ‘The Idea of Progress’ (published in
1979) Robert Nisbet, an American sociologist, suggested:
‘Disillusionment with
science and technology is very much a part of the intellectual landscape, and
it would be a rash soul indeed who declared it a purely peripheral and
transitory thing’.
It would probably be fair to say that disillusionment with
science and technology is now fairly common among the general populace of high
income countries. Data from World Values Surveys conducted in 2005-08 show that
the percentages who completely agree with the proposition that science and
technology are making our lives healthier, easier and more comfortable are only
around 14% in Australia, 11% in the US and 6% in Japan. The corresponding
percentages are much higher for countries with lower incomes: 31% for Mexico
and China and 40% for Indonesia.
Nisbet argued that the idea of progress was born of Greek
imagery and is central to Christianity with its emphasis on hope - to be given
gratification in this world as well as the next. He observes that rationalist-secular
confidence, once so great in Western society, has been fast-diminishing as
a result of boredom with the goods, material and psychic, provided by modernity
as well as disillusionment with science and technology. In his concluding
paragraph he speculates that a renascence of religion might ‘fill the vacuum
brought on by those elements of modernity … and with this, a shoring-up of the
idea of progress from past to future’.
Nisbet seems to be suggesting that belief in progress involves
faith. It arose from religious faith and may return to those roots as
enthusiasm for science and technology wanes.
Does belief in progress have to involve faith? For a couple
of centuries in western countries enthusiasm for technological progress did
involve faith. It was akin to religious faith, with doctrines about the inevitability
of progress – in some accounts even according to laws of evolution or laws of
history. It is possible, however, to believe that, on balance technological
advances are beneficial, without having much confidence that they will necessarily
make our lives healthier, easier and more comfortable.
Data in the World Values surveys on whether it would be a
good or bad thing if there was more emphasis on technology in future may
reflect a widespread belief that, on balance, technological advances are
beneficial. Despite their reluctance to agree completely that technology is
making their lives better, only a small percentage of people in high income
countries say that more emphasis on technology would be a bad thing – and the
percentages don’t differ in any obvious way from those for low income countries.
(The relevant percentages for Australia, US, Japan, Mexico, China and Indonesia
are 6%, 7%, 5%, 7%,1% and 14% respectively.)
It seems to me that Karl Popper’s institutional theory of
scientific and technological progress provides an appropriate framework in
which to consider the possibility of progress. The basis of Popper’s theory is
that there are ‘conditions for progress’ and hence conditions under which
progress may be arrested. Popper emphasized that science is based on free
competition and thought:
‘If the growth of reason is to continue, and human
rationality to survive, then the diversity of individuals and their opinions,
aims, and purposes must never be interfered with (except in extreme cases where
political freedom is endangered). Even the emotionally satisfying appeal for
a common purpose, however excellent, is an appeal to abandon all
rival moral opinions and the cross-criticisms and arguments to which they give
rise. It is an appeal to abandon rational thought’.
Popper concluded:
‘The mainspring of evolution and progress is the variety of
the material which may become subject to selection. So far as human evolution
is concerned it is the 'freedom to be odd and unlike one's neighbour'--'to
disagree with the majority, and go one's own way'. Holistic control, which
must lead to the equalization not of human rights but of human minds, would
mean the end of progress’ (‘The Poverty of Historicism’, 1957, Chapter IV).