I think many people who have some knowledge of the
views of Ayn Rand and Friedrich Hayek have the impression that they had vastly
different opinions on the role of reason. I certainly had that impression until
recently.
I have changed my mind since reading Ayn Rand: The Russian Radical, by Chris Sciabarra.
In what follows, I begin by explaining why I had the
impression that Rand and Hayek had vastly different views about reason, then outline
why Sciabarra considers their views are similar in some respects, and follow
that by attempting to identify the most important area of difference between
them.
Opposing views?
The best way
to explain why I thought Ayn Rand and Friedrich Hayek had vastly different
views about reason is via some quotes.
Rand wrote:
“Rationality is man’s basic virtue, the source of all his other virtues.”
“The virtue of Rationality means the recognition and acceptance of reason as one’s only source of knowledge, one’s only judge of values and one’s only guide to action.” (Quotes from The Virtue of Selfishness, 1961, 31)
Hayek wrote:
“Like all other values, our morals are not a product but a presupposition of reason, part of the ends which our intellect has been developed to serve. At any one stage of our evolution, the system of values into which we are born supplies the ends which our reason must serve.” (The Constitution of Liberty, 1960, 63)
Chris Sciabarra
notes that Rand recognized that individuals tacitly absorb the dominant values
and ideas of the culture in which they live. (193) They develop the essentials
of a “subconscious philosophy” from the earliest impressions of their
childhood. (298) However, she saw each individual’s articulation of values and
attitudes as a means towards rational integration or alteration, and analysis of
values and attitudes at a social level as a means toward their explicit
articulation or transcendence. (299)
While Hayek argued
that reason helps us to observe social rules that enable us to get along with
one another, he also argued that coercion to ensure compliance with those rules
should be minimal. That was not only because coercion as such is bad, but
because it is often desirable that social rules “should be observed only in
most instances and that the individual should be able to transgress them when
it seems to him worthwhile to incur the odium which this will cause”. He saw
the system of values into which we are born as having emerged via social
evolution. (COL, 58-9) He noted that “the existence of individuals and groups simultaneously
observing partially different rules provides the opportunity for the selection
of the more effective ones”. (COL, 63)
Hayek also
recognized that “we must always strive to improve our institutions”, thus
allowing for the possibility that conscious efforts in that direction could be
successful. However, he suggested that we “can never synthetically construct a
new body of moral rules” and “must take for granted much that we do not
understand”. (COL, 63)
It seems to
me that although Rand was more optimistic than was Hayek about the role of
reason in enabling improvements in cultural values, their views about the role
of reason were not diametrically opposed. Both recognized that individuals may have
good reasons to question the dominant values of the culture in which they live.
Similar
views about rationalism
Chris Sciabarra notes that Ayn Rand saw knowledge as
the product of a conceptual integration of the facts of reality. She agreed
with rationalists that human awareness is distinctly conceptual but departed
from their view because they based their analyses on “floating abstractions” –
dogmatic acontextual premises - rather than on concepts with perceptual roots. Leonard
Peikoff, Rand’s close associate, has argued that rationalists pretend to have
omniscience.
Sciabarra
suggests that Rand and
her intellectual allies would have agreed with Hayek’s assessment that
constructivist rationalism – the belief that deliberately planned social
constructions produce outcomes that are superior to those of the spontaneous
order of a free society - is an inappropriate extension of the Enlightenment
faith in reason. He suggests that the crux of both Rand’s and Hayek’s critique
of rationalism is as follows:
“The failure of rationalism was not a failure of reason. By ascribing to human beings the attributes of an omniscient deity, and then condemning human reason for not fulfilling this ideal, rationalists attack the genuine legitimacy of human cognition. Rand argued that this destructive pattern is reproduced by the advocates of altruism, who erect an impossible, self-abnegating standard of morality and then indict humanity for not being able to live up to it.” (212)
Hayek
observed that constructivist rationalists tend to base their case on the
synoptic delusion, “the fiction that all the relevant facts are known to some
one mind, and that it is possible to construct from this knowledge of the
particulars a desirable social order”. There is additional discussion of
Hayek’s view of constructivist rationalism my recent essay: Did Hayek acknowledge the importance
of individual self-direction in his vision of spontaneous order?
The most
important difference?
I think the
most important difference between Hayek and Rand about the role of reason concerns
their differing views about the desirability of articulation of the rules underlying
skills and customs of thought. As Sciabarra explains, Hayek acknowledged that the
articulation of principles can be useful in transmitting know-how but noted
that people often pass on know-how from generation to generation without being
able to articulate the underlying principles involved. He quotes Hayek:
“Man has more often learnt to do the right thing without comprehending why it was the right thing, and he is still more often served by custom than by understanding.” (197-8)
Sciabarra
points out that Rand believed that the articulation process was essential in
the realm of morality because it enabled individuals not only to do the right
thing but to know why it was the right thing to do. Rand held that an
articulated philosophy is necessary for efficacious living: to live
efficaciously it is necessary to choose, to choose it is necessary to define
values, to define values it is necessary to know one’s own nature and the
nature of the world. (200)
Rand proclaimed
that the standard of value of the Objectivist ethics is “man’s life, or
that which is required for man’s survival qua man”:
“Man has to be man—by choice; he has to hold his life as a value—by choice; he has to learn to sustain it—by choice; he has to discover the values it requires and practice his virtues—by choice.” (The Virtue of Selfishness, 28)
Personal
perspective
I think Ayn Rand
went too far in her assertions about choice and Friedrich Hayek went to too far
in his assertions about the limits of human understanding.
I find it
difficult to comprehend Rand’s assertion that humans have to choose to live. Does a new-born baby choose whether to accept the nourishment being
offered by his or her mother?
Some of Rand’s
followers have attempted to explain that the choice to live is a fact inherent
in the conditional nature of human life itself, but that seems to me to cloud
the meaning of choice, and make it difficult to distinguish a choice from a survival
instinct.
As I see it,
rather than choosing whether to live or not live, it is more in accord with
human nature for individuals to seek to discover or recognize what it means to
be a human. As Henry Veatch wrote:
“We could say that this natural end or natural disposition of a human being is something pre-rational or pre-intelligent: it is just a fact that reason can do no more than recognize. And yet – and here is the decisive point – having come to recognize this pre-rational and pre-intelligent end, our human intelligence then sees that it is man’s natural end and hence the proper end for a human being to seek. It thus becomes an end which we do not seek merely in fact and automatically, toward which we are impelled uncritically and unreflectingly, but rather an end that we see that we have reason to seek and which we recognize as being the right and proper end for us as human beings.” (Rational Man, 79)
It is
necessary to be aware of your natural end as a human being before making
choices about what that potential means for the way you live your life.
In my recent post about Friedrich Hayek, referred to
earlier, I suggested that he sometimes went too far in downplaying the ability
of humans to understand the significance of abstract rules. I
argued that most people
are capable of understanding the purposes served by rules of just conduct and
that it makes more sense to explain those purposes than to suggest that
reverence for the traditional should be sufficient reason for compliance.
Conclusions
The views
that Ayn Rand and Friedrich Hayek held about the role of reason are not as far
apart as I had thought them to be prior to reading Chris Sciabarra’s book, Ayn
Rand: The Russian Radical.
Rand was
more optimistic than Hayek about the role of reason in enabling improvements in
cultural values but they both recognized that individuals may have good reasons
to question the dominant culture in which they live.
Sciabarra argues
that Rand’s intellectual allies would agree with Hayek’s denunciation of the
constructivist rationalism of those who believe they knew enough about human
nature to plan a perfect society. Rand’s allies also condemn rationalists for
ascribing to humans the attributes of an omniscient deity.
In my view,
the most significant difference between the views of Rand and Hayek concerns the
desirability of articulation of reasons for adherence to moral rules. I
agree with Rand on that point.
Despite my
disagreements with some of the views of both Rand and Hayek on the role of
reason, I agree with what I see as the central elements of their views on this
topic. I strongly support Rand’s view that it is necessary for
individuals to have an articulated philosophy if they are to live
efficaciously, and I strongly support Hayek’s denunciation of constructivist
rationalism.