Social cooperation is the means by which each of us can
pursue our own ends to the greatest extent possible by engaging voluntarily in
mutually beneficial activities with others. It requires respect for the rights
of other people. (For a more complete explanation, see: Henry Hazlitt, ‘The Foundations of Morality’.)
One way to open up the question of whether a powerful
interest group could form around the ideals of social cooperation is to think about
the way people consider public policy issues in democracies. Different people
are clearly motivated by a wide range of different considerations when they
engage in discussion of public policy issues. Their motives are often not
widely shared in the broader community. For example people are often motivated
by self-interest (impacts on income, wealth, educational opportunities for
children, availability of health services etc.) or by other special interests
(religious beliefs, environmental concerns, helping the needy, prevention of
animal cruelty, gay rights etc.). When their motives are not widely shared, individuals
have an incentive to downplay them and to use arguments that might be
persuasive to the public at large when presenting their views in public debate.
For example, a person who wanted to argue for more help to the needy might put
the argument that this is a desirable form of social insurance for everyone – that
for the most part those in need are like everyone else except for the
misfortunes in their lives.
Even though people come to the public discussion of issues
with a wide range of different personal interests, the discussion tends to
centre on social consequences i.e. the question of whether policy options are
consistent with the kind of society they want to live in. The issue of social
cooperation is viewed by all participants as being of fundamental importance –
options are taken off the table if they are not consistent with respect for the
rights of all citizens. There are differences of view about the weight that
should be placed on different objectives, such as making opportunities more
equal or providing greater economic security, but there is widespread
acknowledgement of the validity of such objectives. Discussions about the
appropriate means that should be used to pursue objectives are informed by
expert advice. As a result of the public debate, opinion tends to coalesce
around particular options and governments proceed to implement those options.
Yeah, right! You have probably realized that in the preceding paragraph I outlined how I
think the political system should work, rather than how it actually works. For
example, I have disregarded the obvious point that a large part of the
contributions of interest groups to public discussion are aimed at marshalling the
people they purport to represent in order to signal to political parties that their votes are at stake. The leaders of some interest groups might even see
advantages in promoting a divisive debate to get the people they represent to
identify more strongly with that group and less strongly with the interests of
the broader community.
In casting their votes, citizens are often faced with a
choice between identifying with a particular interest group or voting on the
basis of broader considerations about policies that are most likely to promote
the common good. If they are cynical about the democratic process and have come
to view it as a power struggle between interest groups they are more likely to
identify with a particular interest group. If an increasing proportion of
citizens think that way and engage in the competitive struggle to obtain
benefits at the expense of others, the benefits of social cooperation will tend
to be increasingly overlooked, to the detriment of the wider community.
In order to consider whether a powerful interest group could
form around the ideals of social cooperation we should look first at Mancur Olson’s
theory of collective action. Olson suggests that the relative power of
different interest groups can be explained in terms of their access to
selective incentives. Selective incentives enable interest groups to provide
rewards or punishments in order to encourage individuals to contribute to their
collective efforts. For example, they may be in a position to provide services
to members including opportunities for social interaction, or to threaten punishments
such as ostracism or even violence (in some trade unions, for example).
Encompassing groups, such as consumers and taxpayers, do not have as much
access to selective incentives and hence tend to be less powerful than narrow
interest groups. (See: Mancur Olson,
‘The Rise and Decline of Nations’, 1982, chapter 2.)
Jonathan Haidt’s moral foundations theory (explained in ‘The
Righteous Mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion’, 2012) sheds
further light on the relative power of different interest groups. As explained
in an earlier post, the basic idea is that the virtues that are found in many
cultures are related to adaptive challenges of social life that have been
identified by evolutionary psychologists. While moral foundations are innate,
they are expressed in differing ways and to differing extents in different
cultures. Political parties and interest groups that are seeking your support
strive to make their concerns trigger at least one of your moral foundations so
that you will see yourself as belonging to their tribe.
Haidt identifies six moral foundations: care/harm; fairness/cheating;
loyalty/betrayal; authority/subversion; liberty/oppression; and sanctity/degradation.
It seems to me that all of these
foundations are often used by narrow interest groups in ways that are
detrimental to social cooperation. The groups can appeal to your instincts to
care for other people in your industry, occupation, community, religion etc., to
seek retribution if you feel that you have been cheated, to maintain loyalty to
the group, to respect group leaders, to overcome the oppression that the group
is suffering as a result of ‘a corrupt system’, and to feel disgust at the ‘degrading’
behaviour of those who oppose the group’s interests.
However, if an interest group is able to trigger moral foundations,
this suggests that it could be powerful even if it doesn’t have strong selective
incentives available to it.
So, does moral foundations theory suggest that it might be
possible for powerful interest groups to form around the concept of social
cooperation? Social cooperation seems to me to involve all six moral foundations.
The ideal of non-coercion - living in peace on the basis of respect for the
rights of others - is clearly related to the care/harm module. The ideal of voluntary
cooperation for mutual benefit involves reciprocity and trust, and is closely
related to the fairness/cheating module. When people in western societies
engage in acts that conflict with the ideals of social cooperation they are
betraying the heritage that enables them to live in peace, with widespread
opportunity and a degree of economic security beyond the dreams of their
ancestors. The ideals of social cooperation are consistent with recognition of
the authority of the leaders of organizations that individuals are free to join
or leave. Social cooperation is all about liberty. In respecting the rights of
others we can take comfort from knowing that we are respecting the sanctity of
the golden rule to treat others as we would like to be treated ourselves.
In addition, the ideals of social cooperation seem to me to
be supported by what Steven Pinker refers to (in ‘The Better Angels of Our
Nature’, 2011) as ‘the escalator of reason’. He argues that the escalator of reason
has provided a basis for taking intuitive moral foundations to a higher level as
education levels have risen and skills in abstract reasoning have improved. As
previously discussed on this blog, the escalator of reason involves ascending
to the vantage point of an impartial spectator (i.e. detaching oneself from a
parochial viewpoint). Pinker argues that a value system in which human
flourishing is the ultimate good can be mutually agreed upon by any community
of thinkers who value their own interests and are engaged in reasoned
negotiation.
Despite all the above, some might argue that a powerful interest
group could not form around the ideals of social cooperation because, like
motherhood, it is commonly viewed as so obviously desirable that there does not
seem to be any need to campaign for it. If we look back in history, however, we
owe the benefits of social cooperation we now tend to take for granted to the
activities of interest groups a few centuries ago (see this post for elaboration).
When the basis for social cooperation is seen to be coming under threat, strong
countervailing interest groups could be expected to form in order to defend it.
Postscript:
For elaboration of these views, please see my book Free to Flourish.
Postscript:
For elaboration of these views, please see my book Free to Flourish.