The liberalism that Patrick Deneen writes about in his
recent book, Why Liberalism Failed, is the set
of principles upon which liberal democracies are built. This set of principles
encompasses the classical liberalism favoured by many who would like to reduce
the dependence of citizens on government, as well as the progressive liberalism
of those who see a role for government in supporting emancipative values.
In my view Deneen makes many good points. Having just
finished reading and writing about The
Meaning of Democracy by Vincent Ostrom I welcome Deneen’s further reminder
that citizens of the United States (and other liberal democracies) no longer
display the intense commitment toward democratic citizenship at a local level
observed by Alexis de Tocqueville when he visited America in the 1830s. I
welcome Deneen’s view that “politics and human community must percolate from
the bottom up, from experience and practice”. I welcome his support for
practices “that sustain culture within communities, the fostering of household
economics, and ‘polis life’, or forms of self-governance that arise from shared
civic participation”. I welcome his acceptance that the achievements of
liberalism “must be acknowledged” and that we “must build on those
achievements”. I also welcome that Deneen’s book is much easier to read than
Ostom’s book.
Unfortunately, Deneen’s book is based on a monstrous error.
The error I refer to is not directly linked to his criticism of globalization
and technological progress, his forecast of growing inequality, or his fears
about “rapacious exploitation of resources”. Some of what he writes on those
topics is in error, but in my view those errors are balanced to a large extent
by insightful comments about education and politics, and his acknowledgement
that “there can be no going back”. (Deneen’s negativity about the modern world leaves
me with a strong desire for an antidote. My desire to read Enlightenment Now, Steven Pinker’s latest book, has suddenly become
more urgent.)
Deneen’s monstrous error stems from his mis-reading of John
Locke:
“Both Hobbes and Locke—but especially Locke—understand that
liberty in our prepolitical condition is limited not only by the lawless
competition of other individuals but by our recalcitrant and hostile natures. A
main goal of Locke’s philosophy is to expand the prospects for our
liberty—defined as the capacity to satisfy our appetites—through the auspices
of the state. Law is not a discipline for self-government but the means for
expanding personal freedom: ‘The end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to
preserve and enlarge freedom’.” (p 47-48).
Deneen has taken the quoted sentence about the “end of law”
from John Locke’s Second Treatise of
Government. However, in the paragraph from which the quoted sentence is
taken, Locke was actually writing about the discipline of self-government rather
than law provided “through the auspices of the state”. The paragraph begins:
“The law, that was to govern Adam, was the same that was to
govern all his posterity, the law of reason”.
Locke goes on to imply that everyone has to learn “the use
of reason” before they can know where their “proper interest” lies. It is in the
context of writing about “the law of reason” that Locke notes:
“the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to
preserve and enlarge freedom: for in all the states of created beings capable
of laws, ‘where there is no law, there is no freedom’ for liberty is to be free
from restraint and violence from others”.
Locke implies that “the law of reason” is
linked to norms of reciprocity: “for who could be free, when every other man’s
humour might domineer over him”. See: Second
Treatise of Government, para 57.
In The Nature and Purposes of Government: a Lockean View, Linda Raeder has carefully noted
the vast difference between Hobbesian and Lockean views of the state of nature.
While Hobbes saw the state of nature as a “war of all against all”, Locke saw
it as being governed by natural law. Linda Raeder notes that Locke’s particular
formulation of the law of nature “carried forward a longstanding tradition that
ascribes an intrinsic moral dimension to human nature”. According to that view all humans “possess an
inherent ability to distinguish between right and wrong” and “every human being
knows, as Locke says, that he is obliged, ‘as much as he can, to preserve the
rest of mankind’.” (Raeder, loc 465)
Why do I view Deneen’s mis-reading of John Locke a monstrous
error? If Deneen had read Locke more carefully he could not claim:
“Liberalism rejects the ancient conception of liberty as the
learned capacity of human beings to conquer the slavish pursuit of base and
hedonistic desires” (p 37).
Nor could he claim:
“Liberalism’s ascent and triumph required sustained efforts
to undermine the classical and Christian understanding of liberty, the
disassembling of widespread norms, traditions, and practices, and perhaps above
all the reconceptualization of primacy of the individual defined in isolation
from arbitrary accidents of birth, with the state as the main protector of
individual rights and liberty” (p 27).
If Deneen had not misread Locke his central thesis about the
contradictions inherent within classical liberalism would fall apart. He could
not claim:
“Liberalism has failed—not because it fell short, but
because it was true to itself. It has failed because it has succeeded. As
liberalism has “become more fully itself,” as its inner logic has become more
evident and its self-contradictions manifest, it has generated pathologies that
are at once deformations of its claims yet realizations of liberal ideology” (p
3).
If we want to understand why liberal democracy is becoming “a
war of all against all” we need to understand why the norms underlying it are
breaking down, despite the efforts of classical liberals to uphold them. Why is
it that people now exercise less restraint in the demands that they make on
others through the political process? Why is it that those whose tax payments
fund transfers through the political process increasingly consider themselves
to be exploited? We can’t blame John Locke, or his classical liberal followers for the failings of liberal democracy.
Despite my misgivings about Why Liberalism Failed I am grateful to Patrick Deneen for drawing
attention to the importance of the exit rights advocated by classical liberals.
In discussing how self-governing communities might emerge, he writes:
“For a time, such practices will be developed within intentional
communities that will benefit from the openness of liberal society. They will
be regarded as ‘options’ within the liberal frame, and while suspect in the
broader culture, largely permitted to exist so long as they are nonthreatening
to the liberal order’s main business” (p 179).
That is hardly a ringing endorsement for the exit rights
that Locke and Jefferson helped to have recognized as core values of western
civilization. Nevertheless, I am grateful for the opportunity to note that the
author is pointing to a means whereby liberalism could transform itself rather
than fail.