I think serious consideration should be given to the
question of why many individuals voluntarily moderate their own contributions
to global environmental problems. Prospects for human flourishing may well
depend on the increased willingness of many more people to moderate their individual
contributions to climate change. Voluntary contributions may not be enough, but
what people are willing to volunteer to do themselves can be expected to have
an important influence on the extent to which they are willing to impose
regulation on others.
A decade ago I suggested that people who voluntarily reduce
their contributions to climate change deserve our respect, but I referred to
them as environmental puritans. I remember being told that terminology wasn’t respectful.
Religious zealotry certainly doesn’t provide a complete explanation of such behaviour.
Voluntary action by individuals to moderate their
contributions to global problems is difficult to explain in conventional
economic terms because people must know that their personal actions will have a
negligible impact on global problems.
So, why does it happen?
So, why does it happen?
The most cynical explanation I can think of is virtue
signalling. Some firms and individuals engage in the behaviour because they
obtain additional profit, or just personal satisfaction, from admiration they
receive by appearing to be virtuous. Even though virtue signalling isn’t
particularly commendable, good outcomes can flow from it. If companies can make
higher profits by presenting an environmentally friendly image, good luck to
them. If community organisations can further their objectives by bestowing
honours on people whose motive is to be admired by other members, good luck to them
too (provided, of course, we are not talking about organisations that infringe
the rights of non-members e.g. terrorist organisations).
Leaving cynicism aside, the most obvious explanation is that
people are willing to moderate their behaviour because of genuine ethical intuitions
or considerations. It feels like the right thing to do and/or they consider
such behaviour integral to their values and their flourishing as individual humans.
It is reasonable to speculate that such ethical feelings and considerations are
strongly linked to perceptions of personal identity. Those who perceive themselves as giving a
high priority to environmental protection tend to see themselves as citizens of
the world. For example, of those U.S. respondents to the World Values Survey conducted
a few years ago who identified with the proposition “looking after the
environment is important to this person”, 83% saw themselves as “a citizen of
the world”. The corresponding percentages were much lower for people who didn’t
perceive looking after the environment to be important.
As shown in the chart at the beginning of this post, the
percentage of people who perceive of themselves as citizens of the world is
quite high in many countries. I don’t claim to know much about what is going on
in the minds of those people. My guess is that when people say that they see
themselves as citizens of the world, they are recognizing that they have a
common interest with other humans in seeking solutions to global problems. It
seems reasonable to expect people who see themselves as citizens of the world would
be more likely to moderate their personal contributions
to global environmental problems without requiring inducement than those
who identify solely as members of local communities, ethnic or religious
groups, or nations.
As implied earlier, some people who moderate their own contributions to global
environmental problems seem to be puritanical in their beliefs about
appropriate behaviour towards the environment. That could be because of they
are deeply religious, whether as followers of contemporary religions or as Gaia
worshippers. It is hardly surprising to see religions urging their followers to
have regard to the global environment and the well-being of future generations
of humans, and to see some of adherents become environmental zealots.
It also seems reasonable to speculate that more people will voluntarily
moderate their personal contributions to global environmental problems when
they observe others doing likewise. They know their own personal contributions will
have a negligible impact on global problems, but they don’t consider them to be
futile because they feel that their contributions are part of a collective
effort. Those who seek to provide an example for others, by making an unusually
large contribution, may see their contribution as having a potential snowball
effect.
The motivations of many of those who voluntarily modify
their contributions to global environmental problems are only weakly contingent
on the behaviour of others. Their behaviour seems to be motivated primarily by benevolence
towards future generations of humans and other species. There is no social
contract regarding voluntary moderation of contributions and there is no
possibility that every human would agree to moderate their behaviour in this
respect in the absence of regulation. An individual cannot induce others to
moderate their greenhouse gas emissions merely by threatening to cease
moderation of their own behaviour if their example is not followed. By
contrast, Elinor Ostrom observed that in a successfully managed commons where
access to shared resources is limited, individual participants make contingent
self-commitments. The willingness of participants to follow a set of rules that
has been devised collectively is contingent on other participants making a
similar commitment and acting accordingly.
An important factor involved in voluntary moderation of
relevant behaviour is belief that human action is causing detrimental climate
change. People, like me, who believe that there is a low probability of
catastrophic climate change within the next 30 years, or so, might also be
willing to moderate their behaviour voluntarily as an insurance policy for
following generations, provided the cost of insurance – for example, use of
renewable energy in place of fossil fuels - is relatively low. More people can
be expected to join the movement to moderate their behaviour if they perceive
that environmental catastrophe is becoming imminent
and/or if it becomes less costly to reduce the exposure of their children and
grandchildren to global environmental risks.
Is coercion ever justified?
Is coercion ever justified?
The benevolent private behaviour of
environmentalists with respect to global environmental problems is often
combined with advocacy of government action to compel others to modify their
contributions. Any lover of liberty would find such coercion difficult to
endorse, but there are strong precedents for it. One readily defensible
movement that has acted similarly in the past is the movement for abolition of
slavery in the 19th Century. As well as endeavouring to ensure that
they did not profit from slavery, members of anti-slavery organisations
advocated government action to abolish it.
If concerted government intervention is needed to avoid a
global climate catastrophe, and if there is enough support by governments and citizens
of enough countries to ensure that effective action can be taken, it would be
difficult to argue that no action should be taken that would infringe the
liberty of those individuals opposed to the intervention. Please note that
there is more than one big “if” in the preceding sentence. I just want to make
the point that it does not make sense for anyone to insist on the primacy of
liberty if human survival is really at stake. In order to flourish, our
descendants need to survive.
Do conservatives understand the motivations of world citizens?
Do conservatives understand the motivations of world citizens?
The observation that environmentalists often combine
benevolent private behaviour with advocacy of government action, seems somewhat
at odds with a claim made by prominent conservative philosopher, Roger Scruton,
in Green Philosophy: How to think
seriously about the planet, published in 2012. Scruton suggests:
"Nothing in politics stands still, and increasingly left-wing environmentalists are dissociating themselves from
the campaigning NGOs, and preferring the small-scale work that both
supports and expresses the low-impact way of life. The movements for low carbon
communities, slow food and permaculture have recruited many who identify
themselves as ‘on the left’. Indeed, this shift away from radical,
government-shaped solutions should be welcomed by conservatives, since it
promises the thing that environmentalists of both persuasions need, which is a
way of sharing our problems and co-operating in solving them."
I think that may be wishful thinking. From where I sit in Australia,
I don’t see left-wing environmentalists increasingly dissociating themselves
from campaigning NGOs. There are some environmentalists who would identify as
having leftish views who are disgusted with the antics of environmental NGOs
and Green politicians and want nothing to do with them. But I don’t see a general
trend in that direction. I do see a trend toward more alliances between radical
environmentalists and people who could be considered to hold conservative
views. I see alliances between farmers and radical environmentalists to prevent
fracking to extract of coal seam gas, because that may contaminate ground water.
I see alliances between residents of leafy suburbs and radical environmentalists
to prevent higher density housing projects. I also see more people with
conservative views supporting independent political candidates who want a greater
national contribution to international efforts to combat climate change.
It is easy to understand why Roger Scruton would
like to see left-wing environmentalists dissociating themselves from
campaigning NGOs. He suggests that oikophilia, the love of the oikos, or
household, is the motive that captures what conservatism and environmentalism
have to offer each other. He explains:
“It is a motive in ordinary people. It can provide
a foundation both for a conservative approach to institutions and a
conservationist approach to the land. It is a motive that might permit us to
reconcile the demand for democratic participation with the respect for future
generations and the duty of trusteeship. It is, in my view, the only serious
resource that we have, in our fight to maintain local order in the face of
globally stimulated decay”.
However, Scruton’s response to the slogan, ‘think
globally, act locally’, seems odd. He suggests that while many
environmentalists acknowledge that local concerns must be given a proper place
in our decision-making, they tend to balk at the suggestion that “local loyalty
should be seen in national terms, rather than as the small-scale expression of
a humane universalism”. He suggests that were conservatism to adopt a slogan,
it should be ‘feel locally, think nationally’. He argues that doesn’t mean that
conservatives are all belligerent nationalists: They think in terms of the
nation state because “they recognize that, in the current environmental crisis,
there is no agent to take the needed measures, and no focus of loyalty to secure
consent to them, other than this one".
I am uncomfortable with the idea that local loyalty
should be seen in national terms. National loyalties overlap with local
loyalties in some respects, but most environmental problems seem to be either
local or global. Humane universalism seems to me to be a mark of civilised
behaviour.
Nevertheless, I accept that the national state is
the only governance system available which has potential to deal with global
problems that cannot be resolved by the voluntary actions of individuals. That
doesn’t mean that I have a great deal of faith in the capacity of nation states
to resolve such problems. Perhaps
voluntary action enhanced by blockchain technology offers more hope over the
longer term.
Roger Scruton is correct in his assertion that
conservatives think in terms of nation states. They are statists. But that is
also true of Green politicians and their ardent supporters, who argue
vociferously for greater action at a national level to reduce emissions of greenhouse
gases. In attempting to push individual nation states to rapidly reduce
greenhouse gas emissions at a national level, Green politicians have caused a
backlash from voters concerned about rising energy prices and the unfairness of
being asked to make greater sacrifices than those being made by people in other
parts of the world. If Green politicians want effective action to avert the
global climate change disaster that they greatly fear, they will need to adopt
more effective political strategies that are capable of winning support from
voters who are sceptical of claims of claims of imminent environmental
disaster, but are prepared to make modest contributions to global efforts as a
form of insurance for the benefit of future generations.
How does Roger Scruton make a useful contribution?
How does Roger Scruton make a useful contribution?
Roger Scruton’s comments about the difficulty of
negotiating and enforcing international agreements to combat climate change are
insightful. He notes that the Montreal Protocol concerning action to combat
depletion of the ozone layer of the atmosphere was successful because CFCs could
be eliminated “without seriously disturbing the economy or the way of life of
any signatory nation”. He notes:
“Greenhouse gases are not like CFC gases. As things
stand they can be eliminated only at great economic and even greater social
cost, and few nations are prepared to pay that cost. By devoting their sparse
supply of global goodwill to negotiating futile treaties against emissions, the
nations are wasting assets that could be spent on co-operative research into
renewable energy."
I think Scruton is both too optimistic and too
pessimistic in suggesting that “unilateral action on the part of a competent
and law-abiding state”, such as the U.S., may end up being the only way the
global environment can be defended. I take his point that the British Navy played
a crucial role in ending the transnational market in slaves, but it is too optimistic
to think that the U.S. could achieve much to combat climate change by acting
alone. It seems too pessimistic to imply that there are no circumstances where international
cooperation could result in effective action against climate change.
Roger Scruton actually points to a potentially
productive avenue for international cooperation:
“If treaties
are to be effective at all they must surely be of this kind – treaties that
offer only benefits, which minimize the incentives to defect, and which
compensate for the principal failure of markets in the matter of global
environmental problems, namely that they do not invest sufficiently in the
needed research.”
Where does this lead?
The important point is that if we want individuals
to moderate their contribution to global environmental problems – either
through voluntary action or by supporting regulation – before environmental
catastrophe is universally accepted to be imminent, then we need to make it
less costly for people to take that action. A greater research effort is
required to ensure that more efficient technologies become available as soon as
possible.