I began thinking about this question as I was reading Ronald
Beiner’s recent book, Dangerous
Minds. Beiner’s main point seems to be that rightwing opponents of
liberty are finding inspiration in the
writings of Nietzsche and Heidegger.
That should not be surprising. Nietzsche inspired Heidegger, who had strong links
to the National Socialists.
When we classify thinkers according to various criteria such
as their beliefs about reason and individual liberty, it seems natural to ask
how they came to have those beliefs. Nietzsche and Heidegger were irrationalists
– they believed that reason is trumped
by claims based on instinct and emotion –
and they were both opponents of modernity and classical liberalism. To what
extent were they influenced by Immanuel Kant?
A friend of reason?
Kant has influenced the way many people think about external
reality by raising important questions about the ability of humans to know the
nature of things as they are. Kant’s assertion that reason is impotent to know
reality may have inspired Nietzsche, Heidegger, and others to become
irrationalists.
However, Kant was in many respects a friend of reason. His philosophy
certainly does not lead inevitably to irrationalism. For example, following a neo-Kantian
approach, Ludwig von Mises asserted that purposeful human action - the
fundamental axiom from which he deduced laws of economics explaining real world
behavior - is a category of the human mind.
Similarly, Friedrich Hayek’s speculations about the workings
of the human mind share with the Kantian framework the idea that our minds
impose an order on what we experience. However, Hayek suggests that the maps
that our minds create are subject to gradual change in response to sensory
inputs. His theory implies that we can advance our explanations of the
objective physical world, and that as we do that we come to ‘see’ it
differently. [Accessible accounts of Hayek’s theory are to be found in Chapter
12 of Bruce Caldwell’s book, Hayek’s Challenge, and in an
article by William Butos. Hayek acknowledges in Constitution of Liberty that
reason “is undoubtedly man’s most precious possession”. He distinguishes
his anti-rationalist position - opposing the abuse of reason in attempts to
control society - from irrationalism and appeals to mysticism (69).]
A friend of liberty?
Hayek counted Kant as a classical liberal, along with David
Hume, Adam Smith, Edmund Burke, Alexis de Tocqueville, Benjamin Constant,
Friedrich Schiller, Wilhelm von Humboldt, James Madison, and others who
advocated limitations on the powers of government. By contrast, Voltaire,
Rousseau, and Condorcet were constructivist rationalists who advocated democracy,
with unlimited powers for the majority. [Source: Nishiyama and Leube (eds) The
Essence of Hayek, 363-4.]
Hayek admired Kant’s categorical imperative (CI) – “act only
according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should
become a universal law”. He viewed the CI from the perspective of meta-ethics,
rather than personal ethics, in suggesting that it “proved of the greatest
importance in preparing the ground” for rule of law in Prussia during the
latter part of the 18th century. [Constitution of Liberty,
197]
James Buchanan referred favorably to Kant’s CI for similar
reasons to Hayek – as an ethical precept supporting norms of behavior that
produce superior outcomes in social interaction. Henry Hazlitt and Leland
Yeager, rule utilitarians, also see merit in a test of universalizability of
social rules, but are critical of the notion of “duty for duty’s sake”.
[Hazlitt, Foundations of Morality, Ch 16; Yeager, Ethics as Social Science,
Ch 9.]
The fact that Kant advanced reasons why individuals should respect the
rights of others counts in his favor to be viewed as a friend of liberty.
However, if he had been able to perceive it to be meritorious that individual
humans seek to flourish, he could have provided a straight-forward argument for
a political/legal order recognizing rights on the basis that it is needed to
ensure that the flourishing of different individuals and groups does not
conflict. [Douglas Rasmussen and Douglas Den Uyl advanced that view in Norms
of Liberty.]
My doubts about whether Kant should be considered a friend
of liberty are centered around his collectivism. He was an admirer of Rousseau
and advocated similar policies. It is well known that Kant claimed that man is
a creature made of “warped wood”. I had thought this was just recognition of
human fallibility, but Kant also claimed that if man is “an animal that, if he
lives among other members of his species, has need of a master”, a government “to
break his self-will and force him to obey a universally valid will”. Kant presented
a vision of a federation of states ultimately living in peace, but that did not
prevent him from claiming that, at the present stage of culture, peace would be
a moral disaster. He argued: “The means that nature uses to bring about the development
of all man’s capacities is the antagonism among them in society”. [Source: Hicks, Explaining Postmodernism, 99-101.]
Antagonism doesn’t seem to me to be linked to any maxims that
a classical liberal would will to become universal.
Conclusions
No comments:
Post a Comment