Chapter 8 of my book Free to Flourish, published in 2012, is entitled “The Greatest Threat to
Progress”.
The concluding paragraph of that chapter now seems like an
exercise in wishful thinking:
“There is an urgent need for innovations to promote a better
balance between the responsibilities and effectiveness of government. The best
hope is that, as more people perceive the threats that democracy is facing,
they will unite to foster the development of better norms of political
behaviour."
Do you perceive that a growing proportion of voters in your
nation are using politics opportunistically to obtain benefits for themselves
at the expense of others? If so, do you perceive that such behaviour is a threat to the
democratic political system? Are you willing to commit to promoting mutual
benefits for all citizens in your participation in political discussions and in
casting your vote?
If you answered “yes” to all those questions, how much time
and energy are you prepared to invest in encouraging others to unite with you
in fostering restoration of better norms of political behaviour?
I still think it is commendable for individuals to foster
better norms of political behaviour, for example in their activities on social
media. However, the idea that citizens might unite to restore better norms of
political behaviour now seems excessively optimistic.
Where did I go wrong?
I haven’t changed my view that the failure of democratic
governments to cope with their expanding responsibilities is the greatest
threat to human progress – the ongoing expansion of opportunities for human
flourishing - in coming decades. Democratic failure seems likely to be particularly
traumatic for people who have become heavily dependent on government.
My analysis in Chapter 8 of what determines whether
democracies can cope still looks sound. The democratic governments that are highly
effective in raising revenue and managing provision of services with little
corruption (e.g. Sweden) are able to cope with greater responsibilities than
can governments that are less effective in performing those functions (e.g.
Greece). The ability of democratic governments to cope depends on the balance
between responsibilities and effectiveness.
It still seems correct to argue that there is an inherent
tendency in democracies for the size of government to expand and for the
effectiveness of government to falter. That is a natural consequence of
unrestrained politicking by interest groups.
I still think Joseph Schumpeter and Bryan Caplan were
correct to argue that citizens are prone to irrational prejudice in political
matters. My empirical work helps illustrate the nature of the problem. It shows
that the percentage people who seek an expanded role for government is higher
among citizens who claim to have little confidence in the civil service and no
interest in politics.
My argument that democracy has survived because it has been
constrained by constitutions, rule of law and federal systems of government
still looks ok. If writing the chapter now I would also emphasise that norms of
reciprocity have helped to restrain interest group opportunism in the past.
I think my discussion of changes in democracy brought about
by increased citizen involvement through talk shows, social media etc reached
the correct conclusion. The changing political environment seems to have
provided greater incentives for political parties to become involved in
identity politics, and to seen to be doing more to deal with all the problems
of modern life:
"The realm of personal responsibility has shrunk as
more personal problems have become transformed into social problems. The net
result in most high income countries has been an aggravation of the tendency
for governments to take on more responsibilities than they can cope with
effectively. Yet governments are constantly pressured and tempted to accept
additional responsibilities."
That quote from Free
to Flourish is followed immediately by the heading: “A basis for hope”.
That is the section in which I made a valiant attempt to persuade myself that citizens
might unite to foster the development of better norms of political behaviour.
There was nothing wrong with looking for a basis for hope. In
retrospect, I was just looking in the wrong place.
Developments over the last few years suggest that there is a
basis for hope in two different directions.
First, it looks to me as though the consequences of
democratic failure might not be quite as dire as I had envisaged in 2012. At that
time it seemed to me as though democratic institutions were coming under threat
in some countries of southern Europe because of increased public disorder
associated with government debt crises and resistance to government spending
restraint. I was concerned about democratic governments being replaced by
authoritarian regimes, as has occurred under similar in the past in Europe and
Latin America.
What has happened is that democratically elected leaders
have remained in place to administer the austerity that was imposed by the European
Central Bank. The failure of democratically elected governments to control
government spending resulted in external imposition of constraints on fiscal policy.
This has been accompanied by a great deal of economic misery in the countries
affected, but outcomes have been better than I had expected.
As discussed in a recent post, I expect that in most OECD
countries the failure of democratic governments to restrain the growth of
government spending is likely to cause debt servicing to become a more
widespread problem in the decades ahead. Perhaps there are grounds for hope
that when they see the writing on the wall, a sufficient proportion of voters
in most wealthy countries will be supportive of political parties proposing
economic reforms, rather than waiting until they are imposed by creditors (or
institutions such as the ECB and IMF).
Second, there is now a stronger basis for hope that the
faltering institutions of representative government could one day be replaced
by superior institutions. I was sceptical about that possibility at the time of
writing Free to Flourish. Since then,
however, it has become evident that blockchain technology and smart contracts may
have potential to enable people to act together to produce some public goods
cooperatively without central government involvement. I became
enthusiastic about the potential for that to occur a few months ago when
reading The Social Singularity, by Max Borders. I have learned a little more about blockchain
and smart contracts since then, and am still enthusiastic about the potential
it offers.
A transition from government to cooperative provision of
services cannot be expected to prevent the human misery likely to occur as a
result of failure to constrain government spending before debt servicing
problems become acute. Over the longer term, however, it may become possible
for people to enter voluntarily into real social contracts that offer better
opportunities for human flourishing than the hypothetical social contracts of
political theory.
Perhaps it would have been better for Chapter 8 of Free to Flourish to have concluded by focusing
on ways in which individuals might be able to protect themselves and their
families from the consequences of democratic failure.
The most obvious way for people to protect themselves and their
families is to avoid becoming heavily dependent on government. I acknowledge
that for many people that is easier said than done. Few people choose to become
heavily dependent on government. Hopefully, safety nets will continue to be
available for those who need them most. Nevertheless,
self-reliance and voluntary cooperation for mutual benefit will provide most individuals
the best hope for economic security in the years ahead.
Good analysis, interesting read.
ReplyDelete