My main reason for reading Politics of Liberty in England and Revolutionary America, by Lee
Ward, was to understand how the English Whigs could oppose the American colonists’
quest for independence. Ward explains why they did not have any problem reconciling
their opposition to American independence with their philosophical views.
Constitutional
ideas that were held in high esteem by Thomas Jefferson and many other American
politicians - particularly the views of John Locke - were on the radical
fringes of political discourse in England. The English Whigs (and Tories) were more
strongly influenced by the constitutional ideas of Samuel Pufendorf (1632-1694)
a German jurist and political philosopher who argued that whatever form of
government a people constituted must be guided by a supreme power that is
subject to no limitations or external force. The British Parliament was seen by
parliamentarians like William Blackstone, and even Edmund Burke, as having
supreme power over the colonies.
Whilst reading about the differing constitutional ideas
being put forward by influential writers in England and colonial America my
mind often turned to the concept of a real constitution put forward
by Sheldon Richman in America’s Counter-Revolution: TheConstitution Revisited (discussed
previously on this blog). Richman defines the real constitution as the set of dispositions that influence what
most people will accept as legitimate actions by the politicians and
bureaucrats who make up the government. He derives support for this concept
from Roderick Long’s observation that “government is not some sort of automatic
robot standing outside the social order it serves; its existence depends on
ongoing cooperation, both from the members of the government and from the
populace it governs” (NPPE, Vol 2, No 1).
All the advocates of different constitutional ideas in
England and America in the 17th and 18th centuries were
seeking to influence their readers’ dispositions concerning what they would
accept as legitimate actions by governments. Robert Filmer used his
interpretation of scripture as a basis to argue that even tyrannical kings had
a divine right to rule. Thomas Hobbes
argued that while individuals had a right to self-defence, life would be
“solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short” if they were unwilling to authorise
a strong government to maintain order. John Locke’s view of the state of nature
- life without government - was not much more benign: in his view the absence
of government to act as an umpire to settle disputes would result in a state of
war, or something dangerously close to it. Locke argued, however, that
government power derives from the individuals who compose society; it is held
by governors as a form of trust; and if governors break this trust - fail to
preserve the property (lives, liberties and estates) of individuals - then power
devolves back from whence it came.
Moderate Whigs successfully advocated a Pufendorfian
interpretation of the Glorious Revolution which deposed James II in 1688. Rather
than asserting that the people had a natural right to appoint and depose their
governors, the House of Commons accused James of having “endeavoured to subvert
the constitution of the kingdom, by breaking the Original Contract between king
and people”. However, the House didn’t even present those actions as grounds
for rightful deposition – it relied on the legal fiction that James had
abdicated. All mention of an original contract was expunged from the final
version of the Declaration of Rights presented to William and Mary.
As already noted, the constitutional ideas advocated by
Thomas Jefferson owed a great deal to John Locke. Tom Paine went somewhat
further by asserting that modern society rather than the classical polis
provides the psychic plane on which moral virtue flourishes:
“Society is produced by our wants, and government by our
wickedness; the former promotes our happiness positively by uniting our affections, the latter negatively by restraining our vices”.
Unfortunately, Paine’s argument for government to be viewed
as “a necessary evil” was not matched by recognition of the potential for
legislative tyranny. Paine believed that legislatures would protect
individual liberty because they would reflect the “popular will”.
Our experience with representative government over the last
couple of centuries should have made everyone sceptical of claims that
democratic constitutions allow the people to rule. The only way the people can
rule is if the real constitution is pro-liberty – and that can only happen if
enough individuals accept responsibility for governing their own lives. In my
view Karl Popper was right to defend democracy on the grounds that it provides
a way to get rid of bad governments without bloodshed. Democracy does not
necessarily help us to choose good government.
No comments:
Post a Comment