Is this an
empirical question or a conceptual question?
If it is viewed
as an empirical question the obvious way to answer it would be to define
autonomy, define realism and then test for an empirical relationship. I have
made a quick attempt to do that in the chart below, using the excellent data
analysis facility of the World Values Survey. The autonomy index used is the
sub-index constructed by Christian Welzel for his emancipative values index. Welzel’s approach is based on survey
respondents’ views of desirable child qualities: an emphasis on independence
and imagination is considered to be positive in terms of the value placed on
autonomy whereas an emphasis on obedience is considered to be negative. The
realism indicator I used is based on responses to the statement: “We depend too
much on science and not enough on faith”. The data shown are from an Australian
survey conducted in 2012.
The chart seems
to show that people who place high value on autonomy tend to be more realistic. However, this is a fairly frivolous piece of research. Questions can be
raised about the relevance of an Australian survey to people in other
countries, the small size of the sample etc. More importantly, for present
purposes, the plausibility of the depicted relationship depends on the validity
of the indicators of autonomy and realism used in the chart.
The
empirical approach to answering the question cannot avoid conceptual issues
relating to selection of appropriate indicators. Perhaps the question should be
viewed as entirely conceptual.
In Well-being: Happiness in a worthwhile life, Neera Badhwar presents a philosophical argument that autonomy and reality-orientation are two facets of the same character trait. (In my last post I discussed
another issue arising from this book, the question of whether human well-being
should be viewed as objective or subjective.)
In brief,
the argument is as follows. An autonomous person is self-governing. When we
live autonomously, we “play an active role in shaping our individual selves,
instead of slavishly following others, or surrendering direction of our lives to
our fantasies, illusions, momentary urges or inertia”. Autonomous individuals have
minds of their own – they rely on their own epistemic powers to form judgements
about important issues, including the issue of how far they can rely on their
own judgement. They are goal-directed and have a reliable self in charge - they
not so self-confident as to be self-deluded.
In order to have a reliable self in charge a person has to be
reality-oriented. Autonomous individuals also accept responsibility for their
actions, and in order to do that they must be reality oriented.
The difference
between autonomy and reality-orientation lies only in their focus:
“The focus
of reality-orientation is gaining the truth about, or understanding of,
important things and responding accordingly, while that of autonomy is living
by one’s own judgements and decisions”.
Much of
Neera Badhwar’s discussion of the relationship between autonomy and realism is
taken up with defence of her view against various possible criticisms. I found
her discussion of claims that realism is bad for people to be particularly
interesting. (The relevant chapter is based on a previously published article.)
The author
concedes that when facts are devastating we might be better off remaining
ignorant of them – some happiness based on ignorance is better than total
misery based on knowledge. However, she is critical of empirical
research which purports to show that holding positive illusions about oneself tends to promote happiness. She points to many problems with the research leading to
these claims. She also implies that it is not possible to draw useful
conclusions from the research findings, even if they are accepted at face value.
People who have positive illusions about
their abilities could also be expected to have positive illusions about their
happiness:
“the
emotions and evaluations that express or constitute their illusions about their
abilities, achievements, and future prospects … together entail a sense of meaning
and enjoyment of life. … It follows then that insofar as happiness consists of
these unwarranted evaluations and emotions, the connection between happiness
and illusions is a conceptual, and not a causal, one”.
I have to think more about what means in relation to neural research findings which suggest that it is normal for humans to have an inbuilt optimistic bias. When I look around me most of the people I see seem to have both a realistic orientation and tendency to look on the bright side of life.
I have to think more about what means in relation to neural research findings which suggest that it is normal for humans to have an inbuilt optimistic bias. When I look around me most of the people I see seem to have both a realistic orientation and tendency to look on the bright side of life.
The author makes clear that she is not opposed to optimism. She recognizes that
self-fulfilling attitudes, whether positive or negative, are a pervasive aspect
of human psychology. The point she is making is that realistic optimism about oneself and one’s
future beats unrealistic optimism – and thus recognizes that it is possible to
have a realistic basis for optimism (as I have previously argued on this blog).
Neera Badhwar
notes that Abraham Maslow and Carl Rogers, leaders of the human potential
movement, viewed realism as central to mental health and well-being. She notes
that in Rogers' view the fully functioning individual is open to experience,
distorting neither his perceptions of the world to fit his conception of
himself, nor his conception of himself to fit his perceptions of the world. I
find this particularly interesting in the light of Rogers’ use of Alfred
Korzybski’s notion that “the map is not the territory”. Carl Rogers recognized
that our maps do not serve us well if they are not realistic.
No comments:
Post a Comment