Inventing the Individual by Larry Siedentop, makes an important contribution to available
literature on the origins of the individualism and secularism which
characterize Western Civilization.
Before I read the book I was aware from reviews that the
author claims that, in some sense, Christianity “invented” the individual. How
could that be so?
Siedentop summarizes his argument: “in its basic
assumptions, liberal thought is the offspring of Christianity” (p 332). What he
means by “inventing the individual” is recognition that individuals have
natural rights, including the rights to liberty, to equality before the law and
to election of representatives. As early as the 13th and 14th
centuries, recognition of the important roles of conscience and individual
choice even led some philosophers associated with the church to recognize that
enforcing moral conduct is a contradiction in terms. The essence of Siedentop’s
argument, is that liberal thought became established as a way of thinking “as
the moral intuitions generated by Christianity were turned against an
authoritarian model of the church” (p 332).
The words, “moral intuitions generated by Christianity”,
raise another problem that I might as well consider before moving on to provide
some positive comments. The moral intuitions that Siedentop is referring to are
intuitions about moral equality and reciprocity – including the ideal of loving
others as oneself and the golden rule of doing unto others are you would have
them do unto you. My problem is that something like the golden rule is common
to the major religions and is expressed in remarkably similar terms in
Judaism, Buddhism, Taoism, Confucianism, Hinduism and Brahmanism. More
fundamentally, the idea of moral intuitions being generated by religion seems
to rule out of consideration the possibility that such intuitions are innate. Perhaps
Siedentop means to argue that Christianity has been more successful than other
religions in cultivating moral intuitions, but his book contains few references
to other religions.
One reviewer, Samuel Moyne, writing in Boston Review, has
suggested that there is a major difficulty for anyone who tells a Christian
story of liberalism’s origins:
“They must explain how, against its original purposes, the
Gospel’s message was brought down to earth, applied right now to radically new
aims and institutions that Jesus and Paul would not have accepted. The reversal
is stark: from a refusal of the relevance of Christian moral beliefs’ to
politics to a revolution in this-worldly assumptions about the subordination of
individuals to hierarchy. You need an argument to show how this happened.
Siedentop doesn’t really have one. He just knows the reversal occurred”.
Siedentop has probably attracted such criticism because he
has been over-ambitious in stating the aim of his book. He has set out to
answer a very big question:
“Is it a mere coincidence that liberal secularism developed
in the Christian West?”
In my view his book should be viewed as answering a more
modest question:
Did Christianity contribute to the advent of liberal secularism
in Europe? That is a fairly provocative question in view of the common belief
that liberal secularism stems solely from the Renaissance in Italy and the
rediscovery of ancient humanism.
This book shows that liberal secularism has some strong moral
roots in Christianity. The author also acknowledges that the development of
market towns and cities played an important role in the growth of freedom (as
have other authors including Adam Smith in Wealth
of Nations).
I found the author’s discussion of St Paul’s contribution to
be a powerful reminder that his message was about, among other things, the idea
that all humans are children of God and the potential of that idea to liberate
individuals from constraining perceptions of their personal identities as defined
by social roles - such as father, daughter, official, priest or slave. Siedentop
puts it his way:
“Paul overturns the assumption of natural inequality by
creating an inner link between the divine will and human agency. He conceives
that the two can, at least potentially, be fused within each person, thereby
justifying the assumption of the moral equality of humans. … That fusion marks the birth of a ‘truly’
individual will through the creation of conscience” (p 61).
The book is largely about the development of the concept of
‘moral equality’ within the Christian establishment as well as among heretics.
Siedentop points out that the concept of moral equality was evident in the early
years of Christianity, and led to recognition of the claims of conscience by
some influential Christians. For example, he quotes Tertullian as recognizing
that “it is a basic human right that everyone should be free to worship
according to his own convictions” (p 78).
It was, of course, many centuries before the implications of
moral equality came to be tolerated by Christian churches - the full
implications have arguably yet to be accepted by most church leaders. The
author takes us through the history, providing a fairly persuasive case that
the roots of Western liberalism were firmly established in the arguments of
canon lawyers and philosophers by the 14th and early 15th
centuries.
My mind is unable to comprehend the book’s discussion of the
contest between doctrines associated with Aquinas and Ockham on the question of
whether references to eternal ideas in the mind of God implies a restriction on God’s
freedom. In terms of the book's objectives, however, the important point
concerns the role of the individual’s will. Siedentop notes that Ockham
associated reason with individual experience and choice, and saw ‘right reason’
as obligated by principles of equality and reciprocity (p 309).
Incidentally,
the discussion of the different approaches of Aquinas and Ockham left me with
the impression that the author is claiming that Ockham rejected Aristotle’s
teleological reasoning. However, the
entry on Ockham in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy suggests otherwise. According
to that source, Ockham accepted Aristotle’s view that humans have a natural orientation
toward pursuit of their own ultimate good (happiness). The point that Ockham adds is that this
inbuilt orientation does not restrict individual choice - individuals are free
to choose whether or not to will their ultimate good.
It seems to me that the author has provided people in the
West with a timely reminder of the links between liberal secularism and the
concepts of moral equality and freedom of conscience. The book reminds us that secularism
is not devoid of values. As Larry Siedentop puts it, “secularism identifies the
conditions in which authentic beliefs should be formed and defended”.
No comments:
Post a Comment