Several rationales for free speech were discussed in the
Finkelstein report on media regulation, which was released in March last year. Incidentally, the report states that it 'must be attributed' as the 'Report of the Independent Inquiry into the Media and Media Regulation'.
Since the report discusses rationales for free speech in a
chapter headed 'The democratic indispensability of a free press', it is obvious
from the table of contents that Ray Finkelstein sees the rationale for free
speech mainly in terms of its contribution to democracy.
I agree that free speech is the life blood of democracy but,
as discussed in Free to Flourish, my
prior conviction is that the rationale for freedom and democracy rests on their
contribution to human flourishing. As I see it, a balanced account of the
contribution of free speech to human flourishing would recognize that free
speech – freedom of expression - expands the opportunities available to
individuals in ways that are not necessarily associated with democratic
institutions. It would note that democracy emerged as an outcome of a process
intended to protect the rights of citizens (including their right to free
speech). It would also acknowledge that the merits of democracy still depend on
the potential of democratic processes to defend free speech and the other freedoms
that provide the basis for human flourishing.
Defenders of Finkelstein could suggest that 'self-fulfilment
and autonomy' and libertarian rationales for free speech are discussed in his
report. However, the discussion of self-fulfilment focuses on the views of
Katherine Gelber – a follower of Martha Nussbaum– who seems only prepared to
defend speech 'that is constitutive of the formation and planning of one's life
in ways commensurate with one's informed conception of the good'. Elitist
nonsense! Who is to decide what constitutes 'an informed conception of the good'?
Are adults who do not have 'an informed conception of the good' to be denied
the right to speak their minds?
Finkelstein's discussion of libertarian theories of the
press is under the heading, 'Social responsibility: a theory of the press', so
it is not surprising that libertarianism is given short shrift. From what I had
previously read about the report, I was expecting that the idea of a free press
would be assaulted on the grounds of monopoly, potential abuse or power etc.
yawn, yawn. But, after going through all that, Finkelstein asserts that
libertarian theory did not provide a workable solution to the challenge
provided by broadcasting and that governments 'found it necessary to intervene …'.
He adds: 'This amounted to a rejection of libertarian theory'.
Gulp! So, why doesn't
Finkelstein tell us what he thinks, rather than pretending that there was no
workable solution other than regulating to control the activities of
broadcasters? The workable market solution, as Ray and just about everyone must
know, is allocation of the broadcast spectrum, like other scarce resources, to
the highest bidder. Does the author have good reasons to believe that would not
enable scarce resources go to their highest value use? If the Honourable Ray Finkelstein,
QC, former judge of the Federal Court and former president of the Australian
Competition Tribunal, thinks that the way government currently allocates the broadcast
spectrum is better than the market solution, why doesn't he make the case?
Finkelstein's discussion of the 'search for truth' as a
rationale for free speech raises discussion of the 'marketplace of ideas'. He
seems somewhat pessimistic about the ability of people to discover truth, but
nevertheless remains optimistic about the benefits of democratic discourse –
subject to government regulation to ensure social responsibility. He ends up seeing
a need to obtain a balance between demands that the media be accountable for
exercise of its power and the need for the media to be free to hold governments
to account.
I found that discussion to be peculiar. Once the concept of
a market for ideas was introduced, it would be logical to expect some
exploration of the nature of this market. There is mention of monopoly and
competition in the rejection of libertarianism, but no discussion of
contestability. Elsewhere in the report, the idea of the conventional media
being increasingly exposed to competition from on-line sources is mentioned, as
is public scepticism about the veracity of media reports, but the discussion of
the rationale for free speech proceeds as though every media outlet has
exclusive access to the minds of its customers.
Contestability seems to me to be at the crux of the issue of
whether media proprietors and editors have power to exert undue influence on
public opinion. The report provides some evidence of media outlets presenting
false or misleading reports, but doesn't provide any evidence that these have
gone uncorrected elsewhere in the media.
Overall, in my view, the Finkelstein report on media
regulation provides an unbalanced account of the rationale for free speech.
This part of the report seems to me to display an amazingly brazen degree of
bias from an author who favours greater regulation to ensure balance in private
media reporting. Some readers might be thinking that comment just reflects the fact
that different people have different views of what reporting and analysis is balanced
and unbalanced. That is a valid point to make whenever issues of balance arise.
In this instance, however, I doubt whether many people who have some knowledge
of the topic would view this report as providing a balanced account of the
rationale for free speech.
In my last post, I promised to review In Defence of Freedom of Speech, by Chris Berg. Unfortunately, that
will have to wait. I thought it would be a good idea to take a quick look at
the Finkelstein report before writing my review – and got myself side-tracked!
No comments:
Post a Comment