‘Courts of Common Reason’ is the title of a book by Howard DeLong (Belcrest Press, second edition, 2011). The book has the subtitle: ‘Awakening the Spirit of 1776 to Form a More Perfect Union’. DeLong argues that America’s political system falls short of the revolutionary democratic ideals of its founding fathers and suggests how current political practices could be revised to be consistent with those ideals.
The author proposes that a court of common reason be
established to determine the ‘common reason of society’ - a phrase used by Thomas
Jefferson. The term ‘court’ is used because the proposal involves establishing an
advisory jury system, functioning in ‘a controlled setting typical of a court
room with unbiased rules governing the presentation of evidence and arguments’
(p 172).
DeLong seems to me to do a good job of establishing that
America’s founding fathers viewed democracy as involving more than just
representative government. James Madison argued that ‘the cool and deliberate
sense of the community ought, in all governments, and actually will, in all
free governments, ultimately prevail over the views of its rulers’. He also
asserted, however, that those to whom the people ‘intrust the management of
their affairs’ should not be responsive ‘to every sudden breeze of passion, or
to every transient impulse which the people may receive from the arts of men,
who flatter their prejudices to betray their interests’. Madison would
presumably be unimpressed by the tendency for modern politicians to pander to
the breezes of passion reflected in public opinion polls.
DeLong’s main source of inspiration, however, is a proposal
by Thomas Jefferson (in a letter to John Adams) for simultaneous meetings of
wards (small political units within each county responsible for schools,
police, roads etc.) to determine the common reason of society:
‘A general call of ward-meetings by their Wardens on the
same day thro' the state would at any time produce the genuine sense of the
people on any required point, and would enable the state to act in mass, as
your people have so often done, and with so much effect, by their town meetings’.
The method which DeLong suggests for identifying the common
reason of society would involve random selection of an advisory jury
(comprising possibly 0.1% of the adult population) using methodology to mirror
important population characteristics as accurately as possible. He envisages
that the advisory jury would be divided into sub-juries, each consisting of 12
people, before listening to argument and deliberating. He suggests that the common
reason of society would be revealed by the decisions of those sub-juries that
achieve unanimity.
DeLong’s reason for proposing sub-juries of 12 people is to
reduce the danger of groupthink or mob decision that he considers likely to
pose a greater problem in large gatherings. His suggestion that sub-juries
should be required to achieve unanimity for their view to be counted is
intended to promote considered judgement. I can see merit in sub-juries small
enough to enable all members to participate in the discussion, but it seems to
me that the requirement for unanimity is too strong. As I see it, if 80% of
sub-juries had 10 or more members in support of a proposition that would imply
strong support, even if, say, only 50% of sub-juries were unanimous in their
support. It would be unfortunate, however, to get bogged down at this point in
the detail of how the proposal might be implemented, particularly since the
author presents his proposals as a thought experiment.
The author bases his argument for institutional change on
the view that the philosophy that common reason should have dominance is presupposed
by the Declaration of Independence and the U.S. Constitution (including the
Bill of Rights). He suggests that
readers ‘suppose, at least provisionally’ that that philosophy is ‘correct’ and
asks: ‘What, then, ought we do to better embody that philosophy in our
political practice?’
I am not entirely comfortable with that line of reasoning.
What does ‘correct’ mean in this context? If it means that the people place
high value on having governments serve the ‘common reason’ of society, then we
should be asking what evidence there is that current practice falls short of
that requirement. Relevant evidence could take two different forms: dissatisfaction
with the extent to which democratic governments take account of public opinion
in their decision-making processes; or the existence of a gap between public
opinion and ‘common reason’ or ‘the cool and deliberate sense’ of the community.
It seems to me there is more evidence of
a problem of the latter kind. If that is right, it means that the educative role
of the courts of common reason would probably be more important than their role
in bringing together information about the views of citizens.
DeLong seems to acknowledge that point when he writes:
‘ordinary polls hardly reveal the “cool and deliberate sense
of the community” that should “ultimately prevail over the views of its rulers.”
Most citizens have not even thought about many of the issues, much less
reflected long and hard to determine their best judgement. What government
officials need to know is: What would the American people think if they had the
information, interest, time, and ability to consider political issues in a
truly deliberative fashion’ (p 166).
I think the opportunity to participate in an advisory jury
system that has a good chance of influencing the future directions of public
policy would provide participants with incentives that would help overcome
rational ignorance and the tendency for people to obtain their opinions from the 'tribes' they identify with. (See this article by Tom Harris for a discussion in the context of climate change policy). Payment for jury service would also help, but could make
the exercise costly. DeLong leaves open the question of the length of jury service.
There would be trade-offs involved in terms of acquisition of skills in
deliberation on public policy issues, allowing participation by a larger
proportion of the population and avoiding unnecessary disruption to lives and
careers of citizens.
DeLong suggests that the questions and problems that might
be put to advisory juries ‘are almost endless’. Examples he suggests include
tax policy, medical malpractice liability, misleading advertising, pay rates
for politicians, safety and environmental regulation, penalties for criminal
offences, immigration policy and eminent domain policy. Towards the end of his
book he also suggests that advisory juries could have a role in revision of the
American constitution.
In my view Howard DeLong’s proposal for courts of common
reason deserves serious consideration as a possible means of helping
democracies to work better. It is obvious that the proposal requires more
thought before it could be implemented, but it seems to me that people who are
concerned about the current performance of democratic governments should be
giving a great deal of thought to proposals such as this one.
2 comments:
Winton,
Excellent write-up of Delong's new book. I was a student of his in college, and was so excited to see this work finally published. Very curious as to how you found it... Nonetheless, I believe it deserves serious consideration, and hope that it will see the light of day as our current democratic machines are falling well short of the founders aspirations in front of us...
Regards,
Ian
(ianmconway@gmail.com)
Thanks Ian. A friend - also an Australian - recommended DeLong's book to me.
Post a Comment